One Nation: The Politics of Race, John Casey
A talk delivered to The Conservative Philosophy Group on
Monday, 28th June, 1982.
Burke wrote this:
A nation is not an idea only of' local extent, and individual
momentary aggregation: but it is an idea of' continuity
which extends in time as well as in numbers and in space.
And this is a choice not of one day, or one set of people,
not a tumultary and giddy choirs; it is a deliberate election
of the ages and of generations; it is a constitution made
by what is ten thousand times better than choice, it is
made by the peculiar circumstances, occasions, tempers,
dispositions, and moral and special habitudes of' the
people, which disclose themselves only in a long space of
time....'
He also wrote:
Society ... is to be looked on with other reverence; because
it is not a partnership in things subservient only to the
gross animal existence of a temporary and perishable nature.
It is a partnership in all science; a partnership in all
art; a partnership in every virtue, and in all perfection.
As the ends of such a partnership cannot be obtained
in many generations, it becomes a partnership not only between
those who are living and those who are dead, but between
those who are living and those who are dead, and those who
are to be born.²
These words of Burke are quite well-known. They express
sentiments which every Tory heart thinks it has known before,
and to which every Tory breast returns a muffled echo. They
have taken their place among conventional Tory pieties,
which is to say that they have been added to that (perhaps)
slightly threadbare stock of propositions, some of which
are mutually contradictory, others of which, if really believed
in, would shock most of the present Tory party. I begin
with Burke, first because I think that what he says is true;
and secondly in the hope that by starting with accepted
pieties I shall make some of the things that I shall later
go on to say less hateful to pious ears than they would
otherwise be.
But Burke was himself not uttering pieties. He was brilliantly
undermining a plausible view of human society which is still
extremely powerful today. He was combating a view of
society which would fragment it, and which would dissolve
what he was to argue was its organic nature. Above all he
wanted to show that we cannot understand our own society,
and our allegiance to it, speculatively: for instance, by
invoking alleged universal principles like `the rights of'
man', principles, which are taken to transcend the customs,
pieties, traditions of a particular nation - of this nation.
Throughout the nineteenth century English writers on what
Maurice Cowling calls 'public doctrine'3 took seriously
the questions Burke had raised, whether or not they agreed
with the answers he had given. They too reflected on the
way in which society transcends `gross animal existence
of a temporary and perishable nature', and the most important
way they did this was in reflecting on the notion of culture
which first assumes its modern meaning in this period. Culture
~was taken to be the whole life of the people, and not just
its highest achievements in, say, the fine arts. This involved
an attempt to understand society and the nation through
the sum total of its practices, traditions and institutions.
This tradition of thought has always had political implications,
since the public institutions of' the nation - religious
and political - are clearly part of the whole life of the
people. And the term most frequently invoked to express
the whole life of the people, including its sense of itself
as a political entity, was nation. The idea of the nation
was of something that could include the life of' local communities,
relations between classes, and indeed all those ways in
which people impose a sense of' themselves upon merely economic
arrangements. Amongst the thinkers who have contributed
to a distinctly English tradition of thought upon culture,
society and nationhood have been Coleridge, John Stuart
Mill, Matthew Arnold, Newman, Buskin, William Morris and
T S. Eliot. To quote Eliot:
... how much is here embraced by the term culture. It includes
all the characteristic activities and interests of -a people:
Derby Day, Henley Regatta, Cowes, the twelfth of August,
a cup final, the dog races, the pin table, the dart board,
Wensleydale cheese, boiled cabbage cut into sections, beetroot
in vinegar, nineteenth century Gothic churches and the music
of Elgar.
And:
There is one problem when we come into contact with a lower
culture for the first time.... There is another problem
where a native culture has already begun to disintegrate
under foreign influence, and where a native population has
already taken in more of the foreign culture than it can
ever expel. There is a third problem where, as in some of
the West Indies, several uprooted peoples have been haphazardly
mixed. And these problems are insoluble.'
If I mention these famous names it is not because I want
to appeal to authority, but because I wish to point a contrast.
Although in this audience, I suppose, ideas such as tradition,
even nation, will not be regarded as just primitive, they
do not find much place in that congeries of sentiments,
prejudices and catch-phrases that make up the liberal consensus.
There has been an extraordinary reduction to the primitive
of political language. Ideas about the relation between
the culture of a community and its sense of itself as a
nation, between a people's sense of itself as a people and
its political institutions, may well give rise to very complex
considerations. But there is a rich tradition of thought
on all these subjects in this country, a tradition that
has obvious relevance to the development of the very idea
of England as a parliamentary democracy. These ideas, which
formed as it were the ground-rules for debate amongst thinkers
as diverse as Coleridge and William Morris, seem to have
sunk into a sort of twilight existence as instincts which
are scarcely avowed, feelings no longer fully understood
even by those who feel them, or hopes which few dare clearly
to articulate. And the liberal consensus, instead of producing
a reasoned critique of such ideas behaves as though they
never existed. It does not offer any clear alternative,
merely a set of sentiments which, it is assumed, all decent
people will share, combined with an extraordinary determination
to suppress any real debate on the issues involved. It is
a sad commentary on the decline of our political culture
that all those ways in which people define themselves as
a community, relate this to their sense of themselves as
political beings, understand the sources of their own pietas
towards their country, the root, as Hegel said, of all true
mental or spiritual life in family, fatherland, state -
should be summed up by so many of the educated class in
one vulgar, and above all banal catchphrase: `racialism'.
But our problem also concerns the Tory Party itself. It
should be a proposition agreed by all reasonable men that
the present Tory Party uses a language of politics that
is hopelessly impoverished. This is above all seen in the
triumph of the idea that what the Tory Party ultimately
stands for is freedom of the individual, rolling back the
frontiers of the State, etc. This again seems to me to be
a form of political primitivism. This and the analogous
notion that Toryism is essentially about a particular economic
doctrine - the free market - which is seen as the economic
version of individual freedom (itself a doubtful notion,
of course), a doctrine which is quite obviously a version
of classical laissez faire liberalism, has meant that it
has almost forgotten how to use the language of State and
of Nation. And until recent happy events altered things
for the moment, and freed the Prime Minister to express
her entirely healthy instincts, a good deal of recognition
of it as a national party had been lost.
To take what seems to me an obvious example: Northern Ireland.
Northern Ireland is officially discussed as though the only
real justification for that province's remaining within
the United Kingdom (or, to put it more cynically, the chief
obstacle to its being excluded) is that a majority of its
inhabitants wish so to remain. Obviously that there is this
settled desire is a necessary condition for its being politically
plausible and possible to maintain the Union. But it is
not a sufficient condition. For as all Irish nationalists
will tell you, that majority was created through the hiving
off of six of the counties of Ulster when in the rest of
the island those who wished to uphold the Union were in
a minority. That the wish of the majority of the Northern
Irish to remain British should be respected must depend
upon facts beyond the mere existence of such a wish. It
must take into account a community long settled in one place,
with a sense of its own identity that is not a fantasy but
corresponds to actual historical events, a people who differ
from a majority of the inhabitants of the island in being
of partly Scottish descent, and Protestant who differ,
that is to say, in race and religion; who have in their
national life an idea of continuity which extends in time
as well as in numbers and in space, and is a deliberate
election of the ages and of generations. This is the underlying
justification for according to Northern Ireland a separation
front the rest of Ireland in the first place, and for using
the power of the State to support the wish of the majority
to remain British now. It is not the unhistorical and unargued
liberal and Wilsonian principle of `self-determination'
which has been such a source of evil and humbug in the modern
world (and was so useful, incidentally, to Hitler in
the 'thirties). In other words their wish to remain British
commands respect because they are British, a fact which
discloses itself through the occasions, tempers, dispositions
and moral and special habitudes of the people, only in a
long space of time. If by some mischance Parliaments in
the nineteen-fifties had legislated to incorporate
Malta within the United Kingdom (and perhaps we all remember
that `integration with Britain' was the platform on which
Mr. Mintoff first came to power), then should it have proven
expedient later to undo this legislation (as it surely would
have), I do not think that the Maltese would have had a
claim upon our honour that they remain British in any way
comparable to that of the Northern Irish. And yet the language
of `self-determination' is the one which nearly all Tories
use to defend the status quo in Ulster. They therefore help
to obscure the vital distinction between an already existing
fact of nationality which may help to justify a subsequent
Act of Parliament, and nationality of a largely fictitious
nature which Parliament may devise in a fit of absence of
mind without foreseeing the consequences, and which might
be subsequently rescinded without any profound moral or
national issues of principle being involved. For instance:
the 1948 Nationality Act; and the 1981 British Nationality
Act.
One other example: the Anglo-Argentine War of 1982 (only
for some reason - I am sure this is symptomatic - it was
not called a `war' but a `crisis' or a `dispute'). The official
line varied somewhat. Sometimes we were fighting to uphold
the wishes of the Falklanders; sometimes their interests.
We were also said to be obeying a United Nations resolution
(of a highly ambiguous character).
Now I say nothing disrespectful about the United Nations
this evening - except to agree with a reported remark by
T. S. Eliot that it is a plot against European civilisation
- but the notion that the inherent right of self-defence
(which presumably Elizabeth I thought she had against the
Armada) should be enhanced by the decisions of such a body
does strike me as curious. The other popular line was that
we were fighting in defence of a principle: I think that
this time the principle was that `aggression does not pay'.
Now apart from the fact that it would clearly be morally
indefensible to send men to their deaths in defence of a
principle, rather than of sovereign territory or national
interest, and especially a principle pulled out of a hat,
(and one which, if taken as a statement of fact is manifestly
false), it is curious that so few prominent Tory politicians
apart from Mrs. Thatcher gave the real reason for the war,
which explains also why it was so determinedly supported
by the British people: that the Falklands were sovereign
territory, perhaps strategically important, and that the
Falklanders were British by every conceivable test (although
not under the new Nationality Act), by language, custom
and race.
It has been well said that `The life of nations, no less
than the life of men, is lived largely in the imagination'.
One way of understanding this, I think, is that nationality,
in addition to whatever else it may be, is a sentiment.
It cannot be reduced to such things as long settlement in
one place, legal and constitutional continuity, shared religion
and culture, because all these things may exist without
the sentiment of nationality: e.g. the Greeks under Turkish
rule. And it may exist without most or all of them- e.g.
the Jews of the Diaspora. But in the case of the English,
and the British, it seems certain that the sentiment of
nationality is inseparably bound up with shared history,
law, custom and kinship.
If the United Kingdom is a prescriptive monarchy in which
the crown derives its authority from its immemorial acceptance
in one particular nation, and if we can take this as the
type and source of all legal authority within the nation,
then obviously the constitution of the nation depends upon
a particular sort of community. It implies at least that
there be a degree of continuity, cohesion, community
of sentiment that makes acceptance of this authority both
truly general and truly `immemorial'. The destruction of
continuity and community must tend to the destruction of
the constitution itself. There is no way of understanding
British and English history that does not take seriously
the sentiments of patriotism that go with a continuity of
institutions, shared experience, language, customs, kinship.
There is no way of understanding English patriotism that
averts its eyes from the fact that it has at its centre
a feeling for persons of one's own kind. The Germans have
the term Sittlichkeit to express the moral obligations I
have to an historic community of which I find myself a part.
The moral life finds its fulfilment only in an actual,
historic human community, and above all in a nation state.
The 'sentiment' of nationality is actually one's ability
to see the community in which one lives, in all its variety
of customs and practices, as issuing in a nation, and to
see that as a moral idea.
Now one very respectable way to refer to all this is to
talk of the sense of race. Unfortunately in the nineteenth
century `race' became the name of a scientific theory, rather
than of a political and moral idea. I have no opinion about
race as a scientific theory, except that it seems no sillier
than many more fashionable theories in the biological and
social sciences. But it really stands proxy for that feeling
for, loyalty to people of one's own kind that I have been
trying to describe, and as such expresses a moral idea,
and a noble one. In Britain it expresses all those forms
of trust that allow the country to be a free, self-policing
state which takes the loyalty of its citizens in peace and
war more or less for granted.
If the account which I have given of the `immemorial acceptance'
of authority within the British state, and the immemorial
loyalty that goes with it, be correct, then there must at
least be a potential problem should a community exist,
in large numbers, which defines itself because of its numbers,
culture and other observable characteristics, in separation
from the rest of the community. This would be even
more clearly true were it to become dominant in the big
cities. Britain is an urban society. The cities have created
modern Britain and defined its character. All the nineteenth
century thinkers whom I have mentioned were greatly concerned
with the condition of the cities, as they pondered how to
relate modern mass society to civilisation. But do we not
have the grave apprehension that the great English cities
are now becoming alienated from national life, and that
the Victorian achievement of civilising them and rescuing
them from the old city mob shows signs of breaking down'
I refer you to an admirable pamphlet 'The Old People of
Lambeth' by Charles Moore.6 I quote out of context, and
only the last sentences, but they seem to me moving and
ominous:
Perhaps the worst feeling they have to endure is of loss
and betrayal. Many of the people I met remember both World
Wars; most of the men have served in one or the other. They
have worked, and raised families and obeyed the law. They
feel they are true English people, who love their country.
They are devoted to the Royal family, and feel they inherit
and live out a life which has the right to be the envy of
the world. And yet, without provocation on their part, they
find most of the things they value neglected or taken away.
As one old man said simply, `It's our country and our Queen.
Why should we be afraid to go out?
This points to a conjunction of `sentiment' and facts:
We come to the problem of the West Indians. There are various
specific features that may lead us to suppose that the West
Indian community, especially the Jamaicans, and above all
those actually born in this country, is structurally likely
to be at odds with English civilisation. There is an extraordinary
resentment towards authority - police, teachers, Underground
guards - all authority. This anarchic attitude seems to
spill over so readily into an antagonism against Britain
itself that it would not be irrational (although it might
be incorrect) to wonder whether a resentment against the
country and its principal institutions is not actually
at the root of it. Then there is the family structure, which
is markedly unlike our own; educational standards that are
below those of all other racial groups, these going with
extremely- unrealistic career expectations; the involvement
of West Indians in a vastly disproportionate amount of violent
crime.
But all this is secondary to the real problem: Because
of their sudden and recent entry, because they are already
a very large community, but above all because of their colour,
which distinguishes them from the rest of the population
in both their own and others' eyes, they have a solidarity
one with another that gives them a sense of identity and
interests different (in their eyes) from that of the majority-.
And if you put the particular features I have catalogued
together with this general feature, then you will not be
altogether surprised by recent events. Last year's riots
were the first really serious sign in Britain of the breakdown
of that Victorian civil order. The first riot was scarcely
over when it was, as it were, officially announced that
it had not been a race-riot. More non-race riots followed,
and Lord Scarman was wheeled out to write his trivial report.
He found various conditions which created a predisposition
towards violent protest, conditions which reveal a
good bourgeois lawyer's bewilderment at English -,corking
class life and at features of it that had never previously
been thought to create the conditions for riot and
arson. These included lack of recreational facilities (playing
fields), the depressing effects of physical decay, and (most
potent, perhaps of all) the existence of street corners
as social centres. The on( - matter on which Lord Scarman
did not concentrate his attention was the fact that the
riots, although as they developed they drew into their vortex
many white youths and looters, some of them unemployed,
but most not, and on one occasion Asiatics, were always
found to coincide, when one traced their origins, with a
preponderance of West Indians. And they reflected habits
particularly characteristic of Jamaica, including that general
rebelliousness that I have mentioned (and, incidentally,
that curious interest in fire). In fact the interpretation
given by the radical young blacks themselves, in the teeth
of bien pensant sociologists, was the most plausible: that
the riots were directed at the police-that is to say, at
the representatives of lawful authority which restrains
the West Indian life style (which seems to include drugs
and other unlawful activities).
This was all very horrible: but I do not wish to say that
the problem about the West Indian community is just a problem
about the possible destruction of civilised life in the
centres of the big cities. (Although that is what is happening.)
It is also that all this offends a sentiment - a sense of
what English life should be like, of how the English behave
towards duly- constituted authority, a sense of what is
civilised behaviour. What it offends is the sentiment that
`this is our country' -a sentiment that the behaviour of
the rioters and their numerous sympathisers within the black
community seemed, in its violence and arrogance, to deny.
What is finally at issue comes out more clearly with the
Indian community or communities - intelligent, industrious,
peaceable people, with most of the domestic virtues. Nevertheless,
by their very large numbers, their profound difference of
culture, they are most unlikely to wish to identify themselves
with the traditions and loyalties of the host nation. Indeed,
they have never done so, wherever in the world they have
settled. They have always remained rooted in the Indian
sub-continent. If the source of authority and the focus
of loyalty in Britain is as I have described, then the existence
by the end of the century of a community of, say, five to
seven million persons in this country who, in the circumstances
in which they find themselves, cannot instinctively identify
themselves with the State will call the actual constitution
into question.
What is to be Done?
I believe that the great majority of people are actually
or potentially hostile to the multi-racial society which
all decent persons are supposed to accept. At the same time
they tend to be abashed, even intimidated by the propaganda
of those who dominate the media into feeling that their
own attitudes - attitudes that would have been regarded
as absolutely normal thirty years ago, a mere orthodox patriotism
- are disreputable. They tend to think, therefore, that
nothing can be done.
At the centre of the moral and emotional objection to even
considering any large-scale repatriation of coloured immigrants
- by whatever means, however financially advantageous -
stands the idea that they are `black Englishmen'. This is
a notion that trades upon the idea of Englishness whilst
at the same time taking away those very features that give
it emotional weight. Had the immigrant community- been here
fifty, eighty, a hundred years, it would look more and more
as though it were composed of Black Englishmen. This would
be still more clearly true if it adopted the culture, customs
and values of the English. But at the moment it looks much
more likely that the large, self-conscious black and brown
communities will turn Britain itself into a different
sort of place. I take it that no one seriously sets the
horrors of the Northern American cities, which have experienced
comparable immigration, before us as an inspiration.
I forget who the wit was who said of the famous American
melting pot that the only thing that melted was the pot.
If we think that something is to be done, then I can see
only two possible courses. The first was proposed by Mr.
Peregrine Worsthorne in the Sunday, Telegraph a year or
so ago. It would be a policy that recognises the dangers
of large, self-conscious separate Communities, communal
politics, division of loyalties. It would involve the breaking
up of large concentrations of immigrants so that our cities
do not become foreign. The end is desirable, but I do not
see by what means it is to be achieved. It would require
direction of labour, and, presumably, some system of internal
passports to ensure that those directed to one place did
not return illicitly. There would also have to be some vigorous
policy of cultural assimilation carried out through the
schools. But for Britain to carry through such a policy
successfully would require a change in our political ethos
as far reaching as that likely to be caused by immigration
itself. It would require a giant step towards authoritarianism.
I believe that the only radical policy that would stand
some chance of success is repatriation of a proportion of
the immigrant and immigrant-descended population. Voluntary.
assisted repatriation is one possibility, and, on the face
of it, the most humane. Voluntary assisted repatriation
was once part of Tory policy but was forgotten so soon after
the 1970 election - in which attitudes to immigration
played no small part, especially in the Midlands - as to
make one wonder how seriously it had been put forward, except,
perhaps, for electoral purposes. One could envisage some
thousands of millions of pounds being spent over the years
in the form of compensation to, and assistance for, immigrants
returning to their countries of origin, taking with them
newly acquired skills and useful capital.
Such a policy would certainly call forth a tidal wave of
protest from the liberal conscience of this country. And
on this matter the genuineness of the conviction would not
be in doubt Nor should one understate what is repulsive
and contrary to British traditions in proposing such large
scale population movements. Yet consider: Algeria was
a Department of France, and had been so for about a hundred
years. Yet about a million Algerians `returned' to France
and were integrated into French life within a very few years.
De Gaulle had the vision, and the cunning, to carry through
a policy that to preceding French governments of both
Left and Right had seemed unthinkable. Yet the French presence
in Algeria was incomparably more profound and powerful and
of much longer duration than the West Indian and Indian
presence in this country. Many thousands of Portuguese left
Africa precipitately in the wake of independence, leaving
nearly all their possessions behind. It was a sudden
and tragic exodus, but there does seem to be a good prospect
that they will settle successfully in Portugal. Again, many
people envisage, with regret certainly, but not with horror,
that a large proportion of-Whites will, in a few years,
leave Zimbabwe for Britain and South Africa. Yet about half
the White population have been there since before the War,
and they have created and sustain the wealth of that country,
and have created all its institutions. Their possible departure
is looked upon as something that can be negotiated about
by Britain for the best possible terms, but not as a nameless
horror. Again, under an agreement between India and Ceylon,
about half a million Tamils will have left to return to
the sub-continent within a few years.
Movements of population are painful to contemplate, and
should not lightly be proposed. But in comparison with these
quite recent events, a scheme of' voluntary, assisted repatriation,
with very substantial compensation and perhaps the continuation
of welfare payments for some considerable time, might be
thought of as not barbarous, but a regrettable necessity
of State.
However there are at least two drawbacks. First: it may
not work. I say nothing more about that except that it is
an obvious possibility, and to eliminate it the sums involved
might have to be enormous. Secondly. in order to promote
this policy public opinion would have to be mobilised, the
political language would have to change, the liberal consensus
- which in this case officially includes the whole of the
Labour Party, the Liberal/S.D.P. Alliance and the Trades
Unions - would have to be challenged and defeated.
_All this could create a climate of popular excitement
that could actually lead to illegal and offensive pressure
upon immigrants of a sort that it is of overwhelming
importance to avoid. Because it would be voluntary
the whole process might be out of political control.
The alternative is generally considered unthinkable in
polite society: This would be retrospectively to alter the
legal status of the coloured immigrant community, so that
its members became guest-workers - analogous to the Turks
in Germany and Switzerland - who would eventually,
over a period of years, return to their countries of origin,
with their pension benefits, property, and perhaps a large
measure of compensation out of public funds. They would
be like the perioeci in ancient Greece; or, perhaps, like
Plato's poets - crowned with olives, anointed with oil,
provided with a capital sum and sent away from the city.
After such a measure had been enacted, it would still be
possible for Britain to decide upon a proportion of the
immigrant community to consider for naturalisation - being
guided by numbers, special skills and requirements - much
in the same way that, say, Australia selects its potential
immigrants.
I need not elaborate on the conflicts that such a policy
would bring about. I do not think that the fact that such
legislation would be retrospective in itself a decisive
argument against it. As Mr. Powell has said, in a sense
all legislation about nationality is retrospective in that
it alters an already existing status. We can all imagine
the outcry that there would be both at home and abroad.
However this policy would have about it an air of inevitability
once enacted, and of political control that might actually
make it less damaging and less inhumane than a voluntary
scheme.
I am well aware that for many this talk has now entered
the realm of fantasy. Here I sit, in a civilised drawing
room, airily envisaging the movement of, hundreds of thousands,
perhaps more, human beings from one country to another.
And I admit that the imagination fails before the task of
really envisaging what this would be like, how circumstances
could change politically for such a suggestion to become
politically serious. It does not, however, require very
much imagination to see what will happen if the present
demographic trends in Britain continue. But perhaps
that is wrong: it is perhaps a complete lack of imagination
in seeing what is emerging rapidly into the daylight that
makes people regard proposals such as these as fantasy.
What is now actually happening in England would have been
regarded as the purest fantasy twenty or thirty years
ago.
Some of the ideas that I have implied in this talk, and
others that I have openly advocated, will seem abhorrent
to many. My defence is this: the state of nationhood is
the true state of man, and the danger of ignoring the sentiment
of nationhood is actually the danger of the destruction
of man as a political animal. Although the courses of action
that would possibly be open to us to preserve the fullest
sense of nationhood would be severe, perhaps callous, that
alternative political philosophy which sees nothing really
profound in the problems posed by mass immigration, but
only difficulties that can be solved by good-will, money
for inner cities, and Race Relations acts, would actually
reduce human society to what Burke called `the gross animal
existence of a temporary and perishable nature'.
Notes
1. Reflections on Present Discontents.
2. Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs.
3. Religion and Public Doctrine in Modern England.
4. Speech by J. Enoch Powell, at Trinity College, Dublin,
13 November 1964.
5. A formulation taken from a speech by J. Enoch Powell,
1978.
6. Salisbury Papers 9.
|